Skip to Main Content
Intrigues: From Being to the Other Intrigues: From Being to the Other

The face-à-face describes a non-intersubjective and nonviolent relation between the other and the self guaranteed by the straightforwardness of discourse that takes place on this side of pure being, the impersonal and anonymous il y a. The subject liberates itself from the il y a, without totally breaking away from it, except when the other faces him.1 Given that the il y a plays a central role both in Levinas's thinking as well as in his determination of the nonethical nature of the work of art, I now turn to its role within the context of the works predating Totality and Infinity. This enables me to assess the full extent of Levinas's condemnation of art in “Reality and Its Shadow.”

Levinas places transitional layers between the anonymous rumbling of the il y a and the order of the world or totality. Logically prior to all propositions, including negative ones, but unable to be itself negated, the il y a serves as a moment of being's foundation. However, if the il y a necessarily precedes the constitution of any world, it posits an implicit, irreducible challenge to the world's autonomy and stability. Levinas therefore defines the il y a as “the impossibility of death, the universality of existence even in its annihilation” (
EE 61/100
).

The il y a is an “experience” whose elaboration is common to both Levinas and Blanchot. Consequently, it shares many of the same characteristics: the presence of the absence of beings, its nocturnal provenance, its dissolution of the subject in the night, its horror, the return of being at the heart of every negative movement, and the reality of irreality.2 For Blanchot, the presence of absence is felt as an expulsion outside of the world, in which the distinction between inside and outside collapses and with it, the subject of that experience. Levinas describes this collapse in analogous terms:

There is not determined being, anything can count for anything else. In this ambiguity the menace of pure and simple presence, of the there is(il y a), takes form. Before this obscure invasion it is impossible to take shelter in oneself, to withdraw into one's shell. One is exposed. The whole is open upon us. Instead of serving as our means of access to being, nocturnal space delivers us over to being. (
EE 96/56
)

Levinas conceives the exposure of consciousness to the il y a as a horror that throws subjectivity into an “impersonal vigilance, a participation” (
EE 98/60
) from which no escape is possible. This is precisely what distinguishes Levinas's analysis of the il y a from Heidegger's description of the pure nothingness (das Nichts) that the experience of anxiety exposes, in which the negation of the totality of entities reveals Dasein's authentic being.3 But while for Levinas horror must be left behind, for Blanchot the nocturnal “impersonal vigilance” gives way to fascination. In this relation the other preserves its alterity and gives itself neither as manifestation nor as presence to an instance that is no longer a subject.4 For Levinas horror refers to the return of being after the negation of all entities has taken place, a return that takes the form of a “haunting specter” (revenant) (
EE 100/61
). Blanchot retains the modality of this return but reserves it for the nonphenomenal core of the phenomenon, the outside, from which fascination has expelled the subject. Unlike Sartre's, Blanchot's fascination does not empower the subject to assimilate the other, nor prevent, as in Levinas's concept of participation, subjectivity from encountering the other.

In De l'évasion and Existence and Existents Levinas analyzes the dimension underlying the constitution of the world. A different order with its corresponding array of forms exists on the hither side of cognition, and the work of art gives access to this order that Levinas calls “existence without a world.” The first analysis that Levinas devotes to the work of art takes place under the heading of “Exotism,” the first chapter of the section titled “Existence without a World.” It is the work of art and the realm of aesthetics that makes it possible to specify the contents of one of his crucial concepts, the il y a. However, as we will see, the work of art not only provides contents for a determination of the il y a, even if this concept is by definition what is deprived of any content, but allows for a shift in the nature of the analysis. Levinas's position regarding the realm of aesthetics attenuates the implications of this shift.

The central operation of Existence and Existents is to perform a reversal of Heidegger's ontological difference through detailed phenomenological analyses of experiences such as fatigue, insomnia and the instant.5 However, there is a shift in method in the presentation of the main insight of the book: the discovery of a paradoxical intrigue transcending being from the obverse of its forms and in the direction of an exoticism that does not coincide with manifestation. At this juncture of the argument, Levinas asks the reader to “imagine” : “let us imagine all beings, things and persons, reverting to nothingness” (
EE 57/93
).

What kind of imagination is at play here? Is this the “disengaged,” “evasive,” “irresponsible,” or “possessed” imagination that, according to Levinas, characterizes the poet? Or the more classical philosophical imagination that reconciles reality and unreality and thus accomplishes a mastery of what is unreal? Does this imagination belong to the level of “passivity” that Levinas discovers in the aesthetic realm or rather to the activity of a sovereign consciousness? In the answer to these questions lies the key to assessing whether Levinas's analysis of the work of art is ethical, in the Levinasian sense of the word, and whether his claims may be valid for an ethically informed literary critique. It is important to remember at this point that the work of art is part of a series of “experiences,” such as fatigue and insomnia. This means that it is one of the figures of desubjectivization and possesses negative connotations, since it still refers to the impossibility of fully breaking away from the impersonal and anonymous being.

Imagination thus comes to supplement and to alter the scene of phenomenology, and the element where the power of imagination unfolds is that of the materiality of aesthetic sensation:

The movement of art consists in leaving the level of perception so as to reinstate sensation, in detaching the quality from the object of reference. Instead of arriving at the object, the intention gets lost in the sensation itself, and it is this wandering about in sensation, in aisthesis, that produces the aesthetic effect. Sensation is not the way that leads to an object but the obstacle that keeps one from it, but it is not of the subjective order either: it is not the material of perception. In art, sensation figures as a new element. Or better, it returns to the impersonality of elements. (
EE 85–86/53
)

Two points are worth stressing here. First, Levinas isolates an aesthetic materiality, the “in itself” of sensation that he locates at the margins of the world—neither inside nor outside—and uses the term alterity in order to refer to what happens in this “in-between” (entre-deux).6 The exoticism of the work of art has to do with its disengagement from the world; it points to an outside without reference to an inside, and this lack of correlation receives the name of alterity.

However, for Levinas not all artwork preserves this alterity. Classical and romantic art conceive the subjectivity of the artist as an alter ego that assimilates this alterity. By undoing the subject/object binary opposition as inside and outside poles of the perceptive realm, Levinas questions a first form of the exotic outside in which a correlation with an inner constitution still exists.7 This is not the case with the exoticism at play in modern art, since it functions independently of objective perception and cognitive inwardness: “[in contemporary painting]… the discovery of the materiality of being is not a discovery of a new quality, but of its formless proliferation. Behind the luminosity of forms, by which beings already relate to our ‘inside,’ matter is the very fact of the there is (il y a)” (
EE 90/57
). Like the face, the work of art offers the “in itself” of represented objects, their naked materiality, as if a principle of deformalization were at play in the work of art.8 However, although the plasticity of the artwork occurs at a different level than the face's overflowing of form, Levinas adds an aside that authorizes bringing the work of art to the face: “the real nakedness which is not absence of clothing, but we might say the absence of forms, that is, the nontransmutation of our exteriority into inwardness, which forms realize” (
EE 84–85/53
).
In the modern work of art objects undergo a deformalization that makes the reduction of the other to the same impossible. This is because the material elements of the artwork (colors, shapes, words) preserve the exteriority of things and “uncover the things in themselves” (
EE 85/53
). This evacuation of form does not signify kath'auto; the in-itself of the thing is neither the luminous plenitude of a presence nor the severe nakedness of the other's proximity in the face, but an obscure dimension of the material world.

The second point that needs to be stressed regarding the materiality of aesthetic sensation concerns the obscure dimension of the il y a or neutrality that Levinas ties to the fate of the work of art and that allows him to claim that the fate of the work of art is Fate. It is possible to cipher the crux of Levinas's argument in this apparently tautological statement since it captures the ineluctable destiny of art, its pagan spatio-temporal schema which, unlike Heidegger's, is not the condition of possibility of truth, of the strife of the world and earth and the foundation of Dasein's dwelling.9 In spite of the alterity that the aesthetic realm offers, as well as the structural similarities between the presentation of the “in itself” in the face and in the work of art, the realm of aesthetics is severed from the sobriety and seriousness of ethics.

It is necessary to surmount the il y a given its “barren, insistent and dreadful character and its inhumanity” (
EE 11
). But due to its inhuman neutrality, the surmounting cannot be “aesthetic,” even if the work of art makes a rehabilitation of sensation understood as an originary quality independent of any object possible. The work of art cannot accomplish a surmounting of the il y a in spite of Levinas's claim that exoticism is a modality of the “in itself” divested not only of its form, but also of its relationship with a subject of knowledge or perception, a subject divested of power, two of the preconditions for welcoming the other.
The exoticism of the work of art consists mainly in a cancellation of interesse, the mediation of being among objects oriented towards their possession or dominion. This is the same type of interesse that, for example, one finds at play in the reconciliation between what is real and unreal and which, as we will see, imagination and certain versions of the imaginary accomplish. In other words, Levinas does not acknowledge the aesthetic interruption of interesse even though it bears striking similarities to what he calls passivity, the most naked form of subjectivity or psyche (psychisme) (AE 116–20/
OB 68–72
), in which the self is already preoccupied and obsessed by the other. In order for this to happen, Levinas must accomplish a reversal of the il y a, and this occurs in Otherwise than Being, after he elucidates the modality of openness proper to the other— substitution.

In “Reality and Its Shadow” Levinas proposes a distinction between rational forms of cognition and the aesthetic realm, where knowledge is not at stake.10 In order to ground this distinction, Levinas criticizes Sartre's doctrine of committed art (art engage´) but also Heidegger's conception of the work of art as the unconcealment of truth.11 Sartre's philosophy plays a central role at that time in France, and Levinas's essay appeared in Sartre's journal Les Temps Modernes alongside a curious note stating, “Sartre's ideas about literature's engagement are only partially examined.”12

Be that as it may, it is evident that Levinas endorses several Sartrean theses in order to argue just the opposite, that art is in fact disengaged and evasive. For example, Levinas subscribes to Sartre's analysis of the image and the imaginary, as well as to the thesis regarding the contiguity of art and dreams. However, while for Sartre a recuperation of the imaginary's negative dimension is possible, the realm of the image is not at the service of consciousness's freedom for Levinas. Art is mute, it is not a language, and if left to itself cannot affect reality in a positive way. Criticism must come to its rescue; it has to speak in its name and reintegrate it to the human order, given that art's temporality and spatiality are inhuman.

In “Reality and Its Shadow” Levinas questions some of the most cherished ideas on modern aesthetics. He also develops two other theses: the originary character of sensation, which he calls “resemblance,” and the exoticism of the work of art. Before evaluating the nature of Levinas's indictment of art, an analysis of the concepts of image and resemblance is in order. “Reality” refers to the natural presupposition of critical philosophy, whose fundament and purpose revolve around the notion of cognitive truth, while “shadow” refers to an image already exiled from the real: the sensible or sensation. Based on Husserl's thetic neutralization, Eugen Fink first introduced the concept of shadow by showing that in the image there is an element of “unreality” which depends upon and is given simultaneously with positional reality (the latter becoming the medium of “unreality”). The distance existing between both regions belongs to the same constitutive intentional act whose objectivity is appearance and not truth.13

Although coinciding with Fink's schema, Levinas disputes phenomenology's conception of the image's transparency. He is more interested in the opacity or shadow than in the luminosity of the image. For this reason, he endows the image with an allegorical function and with the capacity to alter the being of the absent object. It is precisely this function that distinguishes the “manifestation” proper to the face from that of the work of art, even if caricature is a structural possibility of the former:

A being is that which is, that which reveals itself in its truth, and, at the same time, it resembles itself, is its own image. The original gives itself as though it were at a distance from itself, as though it were withdrawing itself, as though something in a being delayed behind being. The consciousness of the absence of the object which characterizes an image is not equivalent to a simple neutralization of the thesis, as Husserl would have it, but is equivalent to an alteration of the very being of the object, where its essential form appears as a garb that it abandons in withdrawing. (RS 779/
CPP
14 7)

At issue is a movement between the two realms that, nevertheless, differs from the Platonic thesis of representation according to the hierarchy and temporality of the original and the copy. Reality does not present itself in a univocal and linear fashion—first its essence and then its reflection, as in Plato—but as ambiguous and dual: its light or obverse, truth, and its shadow or reverse, its nontruth. This shadow precedes the luminous concept and neutralizes its reference to the apprehended object. The image or shadow subtracts itself from idealization; it is a nonconceptual sensation. In the image, the object becomes a nonobject; it remains at a distance, withdrawn or altered, without, however, being neutralized as in the phenomenological reduction that favors the image's resemblance: “a represented object, by the simple fact of becoming an image, is converted into a nonobject…. The disincarnation of reality by an image is not equivalent to a simple diminution of degree. It belongs to an ontological dimension where commerce with reality is a rhythm” (RS 776/
CPP 5
).
When descending to the bottom of life and once the zone bathed by the light of the concept is left behind, it is possible to discover an obscure and ungraspable essence different from the “essence revealed in truth” (RS 780/
CPP 7
). In chapter 3 I showed that in Heidegger the work of art is an allegory of truth, of its uncanny “origination” (Sprung), the schematism of what gives beings their “outlook” by bringing their being into unconcealment. The truth of the work of art also unfolds as the strife between world and earth through which a ground for human beings may be secured.15 For Levinas, however, the work of art is world-less, exotic, and thus does not secure any autochthony; it leads to a dispossession of the self (soi), since the il y a is its unique and final destination.

As we saw in the previous chapter, for Levinas the fundamental determination of existence is not the relation with being (neither an “in itself,” nor a “for itself”) but rather the “for-the-other” (pour-l'autre), of which the face is its basic instantiation. It is a question of preserving the trace of transcendence of which the human face bears witness, a trace that does not belong to the economy of the same, to being or truth (alêtheia). Therefore, what is at issue for Levinas is revelation and whether the work of art is up to the task of preserving the trace of the infinite.

Unlike the unconcealment of truth, revelation announces the manifestation of a hidden reality, which is as such inapprehensible by sensation. The face enables the invisible to be seen, not as a full visible phenomenon, but as what withdraws into its non-phenomenality. To assess whether the work of art can preserve the infinite, it is necessary to focus on sensation's nontruth and to make its difference from the essence of truth explicit. Levinas calls this obscure and ungraspable essence shadow or resemblance and distinguishes it from Heidegger's “letting be” (Seinlassen), since sensation does not reveal our being-in-the-world where “objectivity is transmuted into power” (RS 774/
CPP 3
). Instead, the originary contact with sensibility opens in its “blind nakedness, to the other.” To this obscure essence, which is a methodological specter of Husserlian intersubjectivity, Levinas adds the mark of an inaugural, passive root (passivié foncière), different from the passive and affective force that Husserl locates at the foreground of consciousness.
The sensible impression retains what is felt and this retention engenders a resemblance that, according to Levinas, has a “function of rhythm” (RS 776/
CPP 5
).16 For this reason, there is a mutual summoning of elements in the image that affects us without having to appeal to a receptive will. When our will awakens, rhythm has already invaded us; we already participate in it. This rhythm is neither conscious—it invades and paralyzes our freedom—nor unconscious, since all the situational articulations are present in an “obscure clarity” :

Rhythm represents a unique situation where we cannot speak of consent, assumption, initiative or freedom, because the subject is caught up and carried away by it. The subject is part of its own representation. It is so not even despite itself, for in rhythm there is no longer a oneself, but rather a sort of passage from oneself to anonymity. (RS 775/
CPP 4
)

Levinas compares this rhythm to the automatism of marching or dancing (RS 775/
CPP 4
). However, there is something negative in the spell the plastic and rhythmic hold of the image exercises. This negative dimension of art competes with ethics because, although affecting subjectivity's autonomy, it does not allow the self to open itself to the call of the other.

To the exoticism and anonymous immersion of poetic rhythm, Levinas opposes the uninterrupted contact of prose, to which he attributes the immediate expression of the face. Rhythmic repetition's rhetorical effect is alienating; it produces an encompassing same in which a departure from the face occurs. The poem's discontinuous expression substitutes the immediate expression of the face in speech; it is a constant rupture and beginning. The artwork's expression (an expression of itself) puts a mask or fac¸ade before the opening of presence, the “in itself” of the author or of his circumstance before the expressive urgency of the other. Further, it delays and leads the other's presence astray, as if writing itself were unable to respond to the other in a face-to-face.17

It is true that Levinas's opposition, as well as his negative evaluation of rhythm, make sense in light of his definition of sensibility's opaque image and of the il y a's rumbling. These two determinations characterize the delay of the classical (pagan) artwork.18 The poetic rhythm Levinas has in mind is that of rhetorical, formulaic poetry. However, he does not consider the possibility that beyond its uniform resonance, rhythm may be both intermittent and discontinuous. In this essay at least, Levinas refers to a concept of rhythm that belongs to a tradition for which perception and the restricted phenomenon of poetic rhythm are the starting points of a much broader investigation. This is a tradition in which the association of rhythm and movement is de rigueur and thus repeats Plato's inaugural assimilation in Laws.

By correcting this Platonic assimilation, Emile Benveniste showed that rhythm should not be confused with periodicity, regularity and repetition, but that it is rather a form in time, which makes the separation of order and movement impossible.19 Benveniste's reassessment paved the way for a series of approaches that go beyond the framework of a restricted poetic understanding of rhythm and beyond the empiricist attachments at play in more semiotic theories of the sign.

For Meschonic, for example, rhythm becomes force and energy, a principle of disruption of the linguistic sign, signifyingness, the organization of signification in discourse.20 While for Court, rhythm refers to the cobelonging of corporeality and temporalization: “l‘élan, c'est le bond en avant, la dimension de l'avenir, le projet.”21 The ictus, the moment when the thesis becomes the starting point of a new arsis, of a new leap forward, becomes something other than a dead time (temps mort); it is a contact, a relation (liaison), or “le principe ordinateur du temps [qui] engendre l'ordre du temps, [qui] produit le temps.”22 In the interval of the ictus both a caesura and an articulation occur, and the experience of time itself unfolds. Not unlike the drives that, according to psychoanalysis, animate psychic life, this experience of time is founded on the fundamental rhythmic kernel of tension and relaxation, awaiting and remembrance.

Although the more rigid opposition between speech and writing that underwrites Levinas's conception of rhythm suggests solidarity with a metaphysics of presence, it does not sufficiently explain why Levinas brackets some of the elements that would suggest a more dynamic conception of rhythm and implements them at a different register. The opposition between speech and writing, however, becomes harder to sustain in light of the ethical performative writing that Levinas claims to have produced in Otherwise than Being.23

Is this ethical writing “prose” or “poetry” ? As we will see in chapter 6, the rhythmic scansion of this book, its “quasi-hagiographic style,” is a type of writing that by unfolding thematically and stylistically in a “spiraling movement” (en vrille) (AE 76/
OB 44
), prevents both the said from being uttered all at once and the ethical saying's synchronization. The reduction's “two times” (contretemps) enables the intrigue of the other to resound as an irreducible diachrony, and allows Levinas to displace rhythm from an aesthetic context and to reinscribe it as an ethical trope.

One has to wait until Otherwise than Being to see this schema of rhythm at play not only at the level of its own textual mechanism (exasperation, style “en vrille”), but also at the level of the ethical tropes par excellence: substitution, psychosis, breathing. In other words, rhythm is no longer an ontological trope, but becomes an ethical one. In “La Transcendance des mots” (1949), however, there are some indications that will help us think through a different relation between the voice of the other and the space of writing. But before engaging in a reading of this essay, we will focus on the image.24

SARTRE's WAY OUT OF FASCINATION. It is time to fully assess Levinas's approach to the image by situating his analysis within the context of contemporary phenomenological analyses of the imaginary, the most influential of which, in the French context, is Jean-Paul Sartre's L'Imaginaire (1940).25 Basing his analysis on Husserl's formulations of the quasi-reality of the imaginary, Sartre emphasizes the negative character of imagination when compared to perception. The image refers back to consciousness's “fonction irréalisante” :

The characteristic of the intentional object of the imaginative consciousness is that the object is not present and is posited as such, or that it does not exist and is posited as not existing, or that it is not posited at all…. However lively, appealing or strong the image is, it presents its object as not being. (I 25–26/
PI 12–13
)

In his analysis of “hypnagogic images” (I 55–74/
PI 41–56
) Sartre introduces a dimension of fascination in the imaginary space and speaks of consciousness's captivity when encountering images. However, for Sartre it is always the case of a consenting captivity. Consciousness ought to be able to choose whether to let itself be fascinated by images: “it is necessary (il faut) that the reflexive consciousness give way to fascination” (I 65/
PI 50
). Throughout the book, Sartre's goal is to safeguard the activity and spontaneity of consciousness when faced with experiences that could potentially put it in question.
The image's proximity to the concept is a constant danger, given the possibility of falling under the spell of a “nonreflexive thinking” that hides the ideal structure of its object behind its material structure: “the image carries within itself a suspicious persuasive power that comes from its ambiguous nature” (I 231/
PI 251
, my emphasis). For Sartre an imagined object is unreal inasmuch as it calls for a split self that has to become unreal in its turn. If there is incantation, magic and spell at play in the image, its pernicious effects are only felt at the cognitive level.

The imaginary object is the shadow of an object that is also endowed with a shadow of space and of time, and consciousness can only enter this world by becoming unreal itself. As the shadow of reality, the imaginary seems to imply a correlative shadow of consciousness. However, Sartre does not grant a positive value to this modality of consciousness. This situation becomes clear when, after analyzing a series of disquieting features of the imaginary world, Sartre dismisses them by appealing to the fundamental spontaneity of consciousness in general and of the imagining consciousness in particular. The integrity of consciousness is systematically opposed to the void evoked by the image.

Sartre's main concern is what features to confer on a consciousness endowed with imagination and the ability to produce images. This ability that goes beyond reality is the condition of possibility of a free consciousness. And, since this unreal outside-the-world is the product of a free consciousness that remains in the world, the negative dimension of the imagination quickly reverses into a positive one. The apparent passivity of consciousness when facing the image yields to the freedom and activity of the imagining consciousness, whose goal is to master both the represented object and the imaginary world to which it accedes through images.

In the end, this proves to be a more powerful mastery than that of perception. It is in this context that the work of art is also defined as unreal (irréel) (I 239), since in aesthetic contemplation “there is in fact no passing from one world into the other, but only a passing from the imaginative attitude to that of reality. Aesthetic contemplation is an induced dream” (I 245/
PI 225,
my emphasis). The work of art thus participates in the economy of activity and mastery. If at first it seemed that the imaginary could withdraw the world, it turns out that its true nature is to put the world at the disposal of a sovereign subject's freedom. The unreal (l'irréel) is nothing but a necessary detour for the affirmation of the only possible type of real, that of a subject master of self and world.26

LEVINAS: IMAGE AND IDOLATRY. Levinas's image shares many of Sartre's characteristics: its negative character, its dimension of absence, its closed familiarity with shadow and resemblance, its fundamental ambiguity, and captivating force. However, while Sartre bridges the gap between the imaginary and the real and preserves the unity of consciousness, Levinas stresses a hiatus in the very structure of being. Unlike Sartre, in Levinas the image excludes the concept and its effective grasp of the object. Contesting many of the received ideas of modern aesthetics (art as revelation, creation, disinterest and freedom), Levinas claims that the proper dimension of art is obscurity or non-truth and that the production of images entails a form of magic. The artist is a possessed individual whose irresponsibility, disengagement, and evasion are dangerously contagious.

Levinas's way of understanding the relationship between image and resemblance is not Platonic in principle since no degree of essence is involved in the distinction between image and copy (resemblance). However, since Levinas's interpretation of the image issues from the biblical condemnation of representation, it enters into a resilient and lasting alliance with the Platonic critique of the degraded nature of the image as copy and simulacrum. His view of the image as erasure of the infinite thus preserves some Platonic features. Levinas's indictment of art, even if its language is that of a “philosophy of art,” is situated in the space of revelation: “la proscription des images est véritablement le suprême commandement du monothéisme, d'une doctrine qui surmonte le destin—cette creation et cette révélationàrebours” (RO 776), that is, from the perspective of the biblical prohibition concerning the representation of images (Ex 20:4; Dt 5:7) and whose most important antecedents in the Jewish anti-iconic tradition are Maimonides and Rosenzweig.27

The Bible denounces sculptures and images as instigators of idolatrous practices: “their idols are silver and gold, made by human hands. They have mouths, but cannot speak, eyes, but cannot see; they have ears, but cannot hear, nostrils, but cannot smell,” the psalmist sings (Ps 115:4–6). However, what seems to be the target of the biblical text is a certain type of image: one whose configuration takes the form of a self-subsistent, closed presence in itself; a complete image in itself open to nothing, unreceptive, unresponsive, deaf and mute: “dumb.” The prophets (Ez 7:22; Mi 1:7; Na 1:14) teach that when coming across an idol one must turn the face (panim) the other way, since the God who speaks to the Hebrew people at Sinai should not be confused with an image or sculpture of human proportions. This confusion entails the risk of losing the meaning of their true vocation: to stand fast in facing the invisible, to listen and respond to it. What is at stake in this condemnation is not the image in itself, so much as the look that one brings to it.

The idol (pésel) is a man-made God and not the representation of a God; its inauthenticity consists in its being fashioned by men. Moreover, the idol is an image (témouna) that posits its value as issuing from itself and not from the object that it represents; it is an image that is itself a divine presence (which explains why it is usually made of lasting and precious materials). In the Bible the idol is, for the most part, a carved form (a pillar, a stele, a burning bush), a category of man-made objects whose names cover a very broad semantic field; all of which have been translated into Greek as eidolon, without necessarily belonging exclusively to the field of vision or visibility.28 Although Levinas takes as strict an attitude against images as the biblical prophets, the interpretations of the Jewish law (Halakha) and the discussions among the sages tend to indicate that the meaning of the prohibition falls upon the sculpting or carving of the human face, since there is a risk of forgetting the invisible source animating the human face. The idol's danger consists in misleading men to believe that they can approach the invisible through the sensible.29

Issuing from an anti-iconic tradition best represented by Maimonides and Rosenzweig, Levinas's interpretation of the image as idol stresses its pernicious effects: its saturation of the visible, its hiding and suppressing of the visible and, most importantly, of what withdraws from it: that whose occurrence belongs neither to the realm of entities nor being. The idol's opacity is pernicious because it arrests the light's descent.30 The god of paganism can be conceived as adequate to the idea because it bestows full visibility without shadow.

The idol thus refers to a mute immanence that leads to an irreversible ontological solitude. The proximity of the idol and the image and the degrading of the image into an idol bear witness to the mute immanence that the beautiful is, to the danger it entails. When the rhythmic incantation of the beautiful image or icon isolates us in lonely satisfaction, its opacity or shadow can pass for the light of revelation. At issue is the mute, dispossessing satisfaction that blocks our disposition for the coming of an “idea of God” beyond the visible, a God that from an unrepresentable, invisible, and immemorial past, fills our desire without ever satisfying it. We are compelled to envisage responsibility in the face (visage) of the other, to renounce the mute satisfaction of the beautiful and finally to speak. Speaking here entails saying “me voici” to the concrete and singular human being, while the idol-image erases the withdrawal from which responsibility proceeds.

For Levinas, faithful as he is to this tradition, the image is an “allegory of being” that produces an “erosion of the absolute.” He consequently disqualifies the image by putting it under the heading of idol, a concept that brings together the opacity of aesthetic materiality and the fixed temporality of the work of art: “to say that an image is an idol is to affirm that every image is in the last analysis plastic, and that every artwork is in the end a statue—a stoppage of time, or rather its delay behind itself” (RS 701/
CPP 8
). The concepts of image, idol, and statue make up the coordinates of art's indictment and are related to the way in which time temporalizes itself in the work of art. Moreover, idol is a superlative and perfect image, the image par excellence. The idol-like or statuesque character of the work of art refers to an instant that does not pass and that “endures without a future” (dure sans avenir) (RS 782/
CPP 9
): “the artist has given the statue a lifeless life, a derisory life that is not master of itself, a caricature of life.… Every image is already a caricature. However, this caricature turns into something tragic” (RS 782/
CPP 9
, my emphasis). If the “disincarnation of reality by an image is not equivalent to a simple diminution of degree” (
CPP 5
), as in the Platonic schema of model and copy, how should one think the term “caricature” ? Does the image's caricatural nature not suggest a degrading or a perversion, an inversion of the classic hierarchical opposition of essence and accident?
Levinas claims that “in the instant of the statue, in its eternally suspended future, the tragic, simultaneity of necessity and liberty, can come to pass: the power of freedom congeals into impotence” (RS 783/
CPP 9
). Here too, as in Sartre, we must compare art with the oneiric realm: “the instant of a statue is a nightmare” (RS 783/
CPP 9
). Against the modern humanistic aesthetic credo, art fails to accomplish loftiness and instead produces a relapse into destiny, an entry into the hither side of time, monstrous and inhuman.

The plasticity of the image, the statuesque perfection of its rhythm in the idol leads to a pernicious time: a time of dispossession of the self— “the meanwhile” (entre-temps). Image, idol and “the meanwhile” are systematically tied to the pagan destiny of art:

The fact that humanity could have provided itself with art reveals in time the uncertainty of time's continuation and something like a death doubling the impulse of life. The petrification of the instant in the heart of duration—Niobe's punishment—the insecurity of a being which has a presentiment of fate, is the great obsession of the artist's world, the pagan world…. Here we leave the limited problem of art. This presentiment of fate in death subsists, as paganism subsists. (RS 786/
CPP 11
, my emphasis)

In the artwork, we face the fate of paganism, as well as its pernicious survival. Levinas's indictment of art is fundamentally shaped in terms of Rosenzweig's critique of paganism.31 This may also explain why he subsumes the concepts of image and rhythm under Lévy-Bruhl's evolutionist category of participation, a type of belief-structure proper to primitive societies.32 Levinas's is a religious indictment of art even if he claims that with this type of condemnation “we leave the limited problem of art.” Indeed we do leave it, because what is really at play here is a condemnation of the “ontological use” of art and, therefore, the essay is much more than a religious argument. The “meanwhile” of the work of art is the “irreversible time” of a present in which “there lies the tragedy of the irremovability of a past that cannot be erased and that condemns any initiative to being just a continuation” (RS 65). This is the conception of “reality and destiny” that underlies the “philosophy of Hitlerism,” as well as Heidegger's ontology.

Paganism subsists; it is the danger of a sacred that is rooted in an ontology and in a conception of the artwork as cultic restoration of the sacred. For Levinas, atheism is just one moment in the breaching of totality and cannot be confused with ecstasies or enjoyment. It is the moment when the self finds its identity again through what happens to him, the encounter with the face of the other, which can only prevent any fusion with being as in the work of art or the soil. The work of art is an inverted revelation, an occultation of revelation, an aborted separation: “l'être séparédoit courir le risque du paganisme qui atteste sa separation et oùcette separation s' accomplit, jusqu'au moment où la mort des ces dieux le ramènera à l'athéisme et à la vraie transcendance” (
TeI
115–6).

In chapter 3 we saw that for Heidegger the sense of the everyday, the meaning of a pair of shoes, issues from the work of art; the essence of the thing is made visible by the work of art in an eminent way as a common presence with the earth. The call of the earth, of which the painting is a silent echo, restores the shoes to the earth's belonging and shelters them in the peasant woman's world.33 The essence of the thing thus comes from further away, and it is the Greek temple that gives sense to the earth as soil on which the peasant woman's world rests. Heidegger defines the temple as the setting forth of a human world in its strife with the earth. The temple is envisioned as human installation which, in letting the thing come into the world, also brings the earth to its own; with the temple Heidegger introduces the reciprocal play of the earth and world. The aspect of the thing that the work of art brings into play originates beyond its usage, in a signification that subtracts itself from the essence of technology understood as the dominant mode of unconcealment: the appropriation of the earth, dwelling or poîesis.

The poem sings the strife of world and earth as the site of the god's proximity and distance. In Levinas's eyes this way of conceiving dwelling amounts to a resacralization of the earth; the peasant shoes and the temple hear the silent appeal of the earth and answer to this call through a cultic configuration. Heidegger approaches the thing, quotidian existence, through the sacred; it is in the temple that the god can be present, but it is by the call that issues from the temple that the light can fall upon things. The world of references or assignments does not end with the piece of equipment, as in Being and Time, but with a cultic consecration: “in its standing there (Darstehen) the temple gives to things their look and to men their outlook on themselves. This view remains open as long as the work is a work” (
PLT 59
). The temple is both the starting point and end of the unconcealment of the meaning of being, a meaning that primarily shines “as in a holiday.”
The call of the earth, whose hearing makes up the adventure of being, becomes the source of an enjoyment of an elementary materiality that convenes me and that comes from nothing (das Nicht). From this initial call the earth's sacred nature emerges along with its historial signification. The earth is the gift of being that the poet must guard; the language of the poet (Ursprache) is an ontological production (the unveiling of truth) destined to a historical people. It is the work of art that restitutes the historical signification to a cultic site. According to Levinas, “Heidegger aura méconnu le caractère laïc dans le monde et la sinérite de l'intention” (
EE 65
); this is so because the sacred in the end endows things with meaning. The call of the earth that the poet hears and guards acquires the sense of native soil only by reference to the bringing forth of the temple, a linkage that has a sinister ring, the premonition of a disaster.
In “Reality and Its Shadow” Levinas frames his analysis of the image and art with two sections on criticism: “Art and Criticism” and “For Philosophical Criticism.” The work of art appears surrounded by discourse, as if it were necessary to mark its borders in order to prevent the reader from falling under its spell. In the first section, Levinas contests critical approaches that see art as a form of knowledge and that “still [have] something to say when everything has been said” (RS 772/
CPP
2). This way of understanding criticism has to do with a failure to assess the disengagement of the work of art at play in its completion; a completion by which the work of art “does not give itself out as the beginning of a dialogue” (RS 773/
CPP
2). The work of art disengages itself from dialogue and communication, and this detachment takes place on the hither side of time, the dimension of evasion that precludes the aesthetic from opening itself to becoming.
The work of art is mute and cannot enter into a dialogue with this type of criticism, which is deficient because “it does not attack the artistic event as such, that obscuring of being in images, that stopping of being in the meanwhile” (RS 788/
CPP
12–13). However, in the second and final movement of the essay, to this “still preliminary criticism” Levinas opposes a “philosophical criticism” whose logic “we cannot here broach,” but for which “the value of images lies in their position between two times and their ambiguity” (RS 788/
CPP
13). Levinas does not undertake the “logic” of a philosophical approach to art because of the need and the impossibility of introducing “the perspective of the relation with the other” (RS 788/
CPP
13). A philosophical exegesis of art supposes a previous ethical determination of being and time. And although this “logic” is lacking here, Levinas pronounces a critical philosophical proposition concerning the essence of the work of art— “an event that eludes cognition” (RS 789/
CPP
13). The work of art is myth (muthos) and as such calls for an interpretation (lógos).

If in the case of criticism the work cannot enter into a dialogue (the idol turns its face against language, it is a radical indifference to language, a pure opacity), it can nevertheless be reintegrated to the human order by the language of “philosophical criticism.” This type of criticism gives life to the work of art. Does this rendering of mythos into lógos not entail a form of theoretical and cognitive violence? Can the simple reference to “the perspective of the relation with the other” be enough to justify a distinction between mere criticism and a philosophical (ethical?) exegesis of the work of art?

The nonimplementation of a philosophical approach to art in “Reality and Its Shadow” does not lie in the impossibility of introducing “the perspective of the relation with the other.” Indeed, all the major elements of this “perspective” could have been explicitly introduced in the argument, since they were either outlined or developed in Existence and Existents and in Time and the Other, before their more systematic elaboration in Totality and Infinity. However, what is truly missing in the argument is an understanding of language that would have allowed some potentialities of the work of art to be conceived in their own right. It is not by chance that in Otherwise than Being Levinas nuances his position when he claims that:

To fail to recognize the said properly so-called (le Dit proprement dit) (relative as it may be) in the predicative propositions which every artwork—plastic, sonorous or poetic—awakens and makes resound in the form of exegesis is to show oneself to be as profoundly deaf as in the deafness of hearing only nouns in language. (AE 71/
OB 41
)

In the realm of art the distinction between the said and saying becomes relevant, on the one hand, only when Levinas manages to find a place for being in the general economy of the “otherwise than being,” and on the other, when his critique of Heidegger is attenuated and the work of art ceases to be the privileged terrain on which to wage war against “fundamental ontology.”34 Only at that moment does the work of art become not only a pure said, able to speak of and against the violence of the order of discourse, but perhaps something else. We know by now that the statuesque (plastic) temporality of “the meanwhile” ought to be transformed into discourse. It needs to be put at the service of the order of time in the same way that in Sartre the anomalies of imagination serve the autonomous self. At this stage, it may be risky to assimilate this transformation with what Levinas calls the unsaying of the said in Otherwise than Being.

Levinas must still bridge the distance between a religious indictment of the work of art in “Reality and Its Shadow” and the ethical exegesis of the given-word (parole donnée) he develops in Otherwise than Being. “Reality and Its Shadow” is a remarkable multilayered essay. If read alongside “Reflections on the Philosophy of Hitlerism,” one finds at one level a dismantling of the myth of art and of the cobelonging of myth and art.

The latter phenomenon is no longer seen as the fulfillment of communication and signification or as the myth of a communal and authentic signification, but as a shadow or a nontruth whose fascination is mortally dangerous and that one must escape. However, this evasion, hypostasis, or process of deneutralization is not the work of an isolated subject. In the subject's adventure to secure a world and to live among entities, there is always a risk of relapsing into the il y a. The process of deneutralization has a new meaning only in “the proximity of the other structured as an asymmetry.”35 Levinas deploys the term deneutralization, which ciphers a movement “that finally let us catch a glimpse of the ethical meaning of the word good” (
EE 12
), not only against Heidegger's ontology, but also against Blanchot.

At another level of “Reality and Its Shadow” Levinas attempts to reintegrate the work of art into the human realm and thus preserve traces of a classic moral conception of art. The work of art continues to be, if not a major obstacle, at least something that keeps disrupting the space of ethics. One can find a different approach to writing and, more implicitly, to rhythm in “La Transcendance des mots,” an essay Levinas wrote in 1949 on Michel Leiris's Biffures. In this essay it is possible to detect some indications of how an ethical writing might look, of how the “otherwise than being,” in which transcendence indicates itself and, at the same time, hides and shelters itself from manifestation, can signify without congealing into an image or idol. This writing of the other must unfold as a clandestine intrigue, able to render the manner in which the “otherwise” than being leaves its traces.

By bifurcation and/or erasure (biffure), Levinas understands an implausible and unheard-of process of accretion of meaning that unfolds by means of a proliferation of associations beyond contiguity, since what matters is “la presence d'une idée dans l'autre” (
HS 199
).36 In the procedure called “biffures” Levinas locates “une pensée pardélà les categories classiques de la repre´sentation et de l'idéntité” (
HS 199
), as its originality lies precisely in positing the multiple as simultaneity and the state of consciousness as something irreducibly ambiguous. These are important features that Levinas's writing will make his own: the principle of hetero-affection, of the other-in-the-same that produces a coimplication of all the major concepts; the simultaneous proliferation of the multiple, which will become writing as “exasperation.” The appositive bifurcation of concepts and ambiguity or the amphibology of the said are all constitutive features of Otherwise than Being, a treatise on the ethical biffure of ontology: the unsaying of the said, the ethical subtraction of the saying from the space of identity or said.
But in this essay all these features are still subsumed under the primacy of the spoken word, which is the defining feature of Totality and Infinity. It explains why Levinas is quick to delimit the potentiality (vertu) of this literary writing by reducing the ambiguity of the biffures to the shaping or configuration of a space (
HS 199
). By bringing together Leiris's writing and Charles Lapicque's paintings without any explicit reason, except perhaps the implicit axiom that “all art is plastic” (
TI 140/149
), Levinas links the spatial and the visual. He exposes the immanent economy of being within which these artistic forms operate, thus leading the philosopher to declare that “tous les arts, même les sonores, font du silence” (
HS 201
).
Faithful to his determination of the essence of art, Levinas speaks of a transformation of language and of its engulfing of images in which the nontruth of being emerges. We are back in familiar territory; the muteness of the work of art was why in “Reality and Its Shadow” Levinas surrounded it with a double ring of criticism. But in “La Transcendance de la parole” Levinas does what he refrained from doing in “Reality and Its Shadow.” He introduces the “perspective of the other” within the frame of an “ethical criticism” of art. If all arts “font du silence,” it is the very impossibility of speaking that, at the same time, elicits a “besoin d'entrer en relation avec quelqu'un malgré et par-dessus l'achévement et la paix du beau” (
HS 201
), a critical need (besoin critique). Criticism is now placed under the heading of need.

The critical need is thus a response to the completeness of the work of art, to its immobilization of time, to the violent immanent holding of its plastic rhythmic schema and erasure of the absolute, even if Levinas claims that Leiris's text belongs to a regime of incompleteness (a post-modern and even a post-beautiful regime). By “peace of the beautiful” we by now know that Levinas means a violent indifference to the other. The aesthetic delectation of the work of art leads us to an “en dec¸a” without hope of redemption, a world already closed and finished in itself.

So a breaching of this always-complete world of vision (totality or being) and the work of art must occur: a resounding, a roar, a scandal—a sound. If the image entails a stoppage of time, a delay with respect to itself, the sound produces an overflowing of the sensible by itself, of the form by the content, a tearing of the world by something that cannot be reduced to a vision and that, therefore, exceeds the sensible: “entendre véritablement un son c'est entendre un mot. Le son pur est verbe” (
HS 201
).

As in Totality and Infinity, the spoken word (parole proferée) plays the role of a transcendent origination of meaning; it is the real presence of the other that matters, a situation

dont le privilège se révèle à Robinson quand, dans le splendeur du paysage tropical, n'ayant rompu ni par ses utensils, ni par sa morale, ni par son calendrier, aucun lien avec la civilization, il conna ît dans la rencontre avec Vendredi le plus grand événement de sa vie insulaire; où enfin un homme qui parle remplace la tristesse inexprimable de l'echo. (
HS 201–2
)
The insular life of aesthetic enjoyment supposes a form of violence to the self; a self-positing that gives itself as a spectacle that only the other who speaks can counter. Robinson here embodies the figure of the chez soi, the self-sufficient self (soi) that in Totality and Infinity is the precondition for encountering the other, a figure of totality; while Friday belongs to the biblical series of the other, “the widow, the orphan, and the stranger.” It is Friday who speaks and in speaking he exposes the constitutive insufficiency in the position of the subject (Robinson): “le sujet qui parle ne situe pas le monde par rapport à lui-même, ne se situe pas purement et simplement au sein de son propre spectacle, comme l'artiste—mais par rapport à l'Autre” (
HS 203
). As we established it in the previous chapter, here we come across the questioning of the self's spontaneity or ethics in terms of a set of premises Levinas had introduced in Totality and Infinity through the concrete event of the encounter with the other.
The artist, the poet loses the privilege he had in Heidegger; he is neither the guardian of being's truth nor the semigod whose signs are “prophetic” and who thus announces the primordial word of the sacred (EH 136–39). In Levinas it is only the face of the other in its nakedness that can teach. By teaching, Levinas refers in this context to a “wrenching” of experience from its aesthetic self-sufficiency—the very operation that, not without violence, Levinas performs upon Leiris's text—the “critical saying” to the other by which art is completed. As in Sartre, “le langage de la critique nous fait sortir des rêves—dont le langage artistique fait intégralment partie” (
HS 202
). While the artist situates himself in relation to himself, inside his own spectacle, the speaking subject situates himself in relation to the other: “par la parole proferée, le sujet qui se pose s'expose et, en quelque manière, prie” (
HS 203
). He speaks in the anarchic language that dissolves the “mythical format of the element” (
TeI
G 140/
TI 149
).

The work does not speak, it is mute, its beauty guards this silence; no address, no message stems from it. One cannot retrieve a fable of the origins, a “poem before the poem,” as in Heidegger, nor hear the grounding attunement as mourning that issues from the departure of the ancient gods and the awaiting the coming of the new gods. By being restricted to the il y a, the absence of a world, the work plunges us into horror, trapping us in an existence without a world.

Nevertheless, the critical need arising from this deadly silence seems to indicate that there is a language that must be delivered from this inhuman hold. The critic is the one who resurrects the infinite that inhabits the finitude of the said. He must elevate a saying that is in excess with respect to the immanence of what is said: “Closer to us than any present, the Unpresentable will not be represented in the poem. It will be the poetry of the poem. Poetry signifies poetically the resurrection that sustains it: not in the fable it sings, but in its very singing” (
NP 13
).37 This is a strikingly Heideggerian formulation, except that once conceived in its relation to infinity, “the poetry of the poem” implies an ethical potentiality. We will see how this potentiality (vertu) of poetic saying unfolds in Otherwise than Being. However, for this to occur Levinas must also implement a different understanding of rhetoric, which he begins to elaborate in the 1980s, as the essay “Langage quotidien et rhétorique sans eloquence” (1981) confirms. By questioning the classical determination of rhetoric as a technique for mastering language, Levinas aims to ground the ethical saying in the empirical order of the everyday life, beyond its determination as the unveiling of being and of Gerede or chatter, the improper or inauthentic everyday existential determination of language, according to Heidegger.
Heidegger approaches the everyday on the basis of structures of existence (care, being-in-the-world) and posits it as an inner possibility of a proper, authentic existence that can only be secured through more essential modes of being—poetry, thinking, political foundation—than the everyday. The everyday, which is “a fundamental mode of being-in-the world” (
BT ¶ 37
), is improper, inauthentic, and is thus conceived in terms of a set of relations and as impersonal existence (das Man) in which a technological leveling down of experience may occur. In chapter 2 we saw that the essence of technology brings into play an obfuscation of the manifestation of being. Only poetic language can reestablish the initial unveiling of being (phusis), the sacred, and grant us the possibility of a dwelling. Levinas's everyday is grounded in enjoyment (vivre de); the ego's happiness is the way in which the infinite posits itself and opens the self (soi) from within. Moreover, Levinas understands everyday language in light of the distinction between said (dit) and saying (dire), a distinction that, as we will see in chapter 6, plays a decisive role in the ethical writing of Otherwise than Being. It enables him to reverse the traditional understanding of language as proposition (dit) to the exclusion or subordination of the saying (dire).
It is in the saying that one must expose “an intrigue that does not reduce itself to the thematization or exposition of a said, to the correlation in which a saying would make the being of an entity appear” (
HS 192
). Levinas subtracts apophansis, the Heideggerian inaugural determination of language as the showing of truth, from the economy of being and transforms it into a modality of the approach of the other (autrui). Before being the manifestation of the being of an entity, the proposition is what I propose to another human being. The saying (dire) is “an approche du prochain” (
HS 193
) beyond any signification; everyday language is that language in which the saying as approach of the other is not absorbed in the said or proposition.
This is a radical way of defining everyday language, since as we saw in the previous chapter, it presupposes that the empirical is already invested by a trace of infinity. For this reason everyday language understood as saying is “a nonindifference to the other, susceptible of an ethical signification to which the utterance of the said subordinates” (
HS 193
). This already means that the “this as that” (the basic hermeneutic structure of signification) is derivative with respect to this noneloquent quotidian language. In the proximity of the other human being, a proximity in which he is at the same time wholly other (tout autre), the signifyingness (signifiance) of a transcendence is born, with its archi-original metaphors “capable of signifying the infinite” (
HS 193
). Otherwise than Being weaves an intrigue of the other with the threads of quotidian language and the potentiality of poetic language to communicate these archi-original metaphors.38 A process of desacralization of the work has began, a separation from the truth of the appearance that is essentially mixed to the true (DSS 90), and which the work of art cannot accomplish due to its inextricable participation in being's nontruth.
“THE RESEMBLANCE OF CADAVERS” : BLANCHOT. It is tempting to read Sartre and Levinas as representing the “two versions of the imaginary” that Blanchot refers to in The Space of Literature. The more conventional version would reserve for the image and the imaginary the dialectical function of bridging the gap between intelligibility and the negative dimension of art. The less conventional would stress its inassimilable negative dimension, its “shadow.” Nevertheless, such a neat division does not hold, since a version (versant) supposes a movement of reversal and, therefore, a certain unavoidable contamination. This ambiguity is not accidental but something that “comes from the initial double meaning produced by the power of the negative and the fact that death is sometimes the work of truth in the world, sometimes the perpetuity of something that does not tolerate either a beginning or an end” (
EL
351/
SH 424
). Therefore, one cannot simply choose one version over the other because “an art which purports to follow one version (versant) is already on the other” (
PF
321/
SH 388
). We could replace the word “art” with “philosophy” here so as to locate this reversal in Levinas's argument.

As I have shown, the Levinasian critique of the image's hold points to a ghostly temporality, a mute and inhuman dimension, “the meanwhile,” which strictly speaking belongs neither to presence nor to absence. Nevertheless, Levinas conceives this negative dimension in terms of the idol, a figure which suggests a form of full-fledged presence, albeit a mute one.

The ghostly temporality of the “meanwhile,” the fact that the “meanwhile” is, becomes the statuesque glow of the idol in which no ambiguity survives. The “meanwhile” belongs to il y a's “elementary materiality” that must be surpassed by the approach of the other human being whose face bears the trace of transcendence.

Blanchot's version of the imaginary shares many of the features found in Sartre and Levinas and takes its point of departure precisely from what Levinas's analysis leaves out: “the position an image occupies between two times and their ambiguity” (RS 788/
CPP 13
). Although Blanchot does not reject the possibility of reintroducing this negative dimension in the order of the day, he is interested in the particular and irreducible negative character of the image. In Blanchot there is neither a call for an evasion of the il y a nor a process of deneutralization. Writing faces this “elementary materiality” and thinking implies keeping watch (veiller) on this movement of dispossession. Literary language is the site where Blanchot comes face-to-face with a dimension of the negative that dialectics cannot sublate, and which he elucidates under four different headings: the experience of the night or outside, the neuter, the disaster and the return (
ED
95/
WD 57
).

One of the names of this experience of the night is, of course, the il y a. While Levinas assimilates the il y a to the category of being, Blanchot approaches its negative dimension as what is on the hither side of being and ontology: neither being nor nonbeing. If for Levinas the ethical reduction of being's neutrality and anonymity energizes itself from a writing that bears witness to the trace of the other, writing in Blanchot marks a “step not beyond” (pas au-delà). It is a perpetual errancy faced with an inhospitable other that one must welcome in the absence of any dwelling place and independently of its inhuman character. Levinas's other (autrui) is a human other whose face bears witness to the trace of transcendence; it is the immanent site of transcendence. But Blanchot's other is prehuman and conceived in terms of the structure of difference, although the human dimension does appear years later in The Infinite Conversation.39

Given that for Blanchot the image is the oscillation of the two versions, or the very deployment of ambiguity, it gives access to the “elementary materiality” of the neuter. It pacifies and humanizes “the unformed nothingness pushed towards us by the residue of being that cannot be Eliminated” (
EL
341/
SH 417
). This humanizing aspect that the image accomplishes in the work of art brings the promise of “a pure happiness” and of the “transparent eternity of the unreal.” In this version, the image affirms presence, even if this is the presence of an absence that it manages to dissimulate; it is the representation of a preexistent object that belongs to a preexistent world.

We are not far here from the imagination's “fonction irréalisante” (Sartre) and from the halting of the instant that Levinas isolates in classical art, but that he interprets as the plasticity of art in general. However, in Sartre the image's “fonction irréalisante” is relative; the image accomplishes the object's negation but preserves the world as its background. Against Sartre and more in line with Levinas, Blanchot relates the space of the image's negation with an “elementary materiality” that he calls the neuter (neutre). It is important here to emphasize the commonality between Levinas's il y a and Blanchot's neuter, as well as to stress that it is a commonality on which they also part ways. One should not forget that in Levinas the il y a's “elementary materiality” must be surmounted, and that this can only occur by the approach of the other. This is not the case with Blanchot, who aims to preserve the neuter. However, since the terms neuter and neutrality are the site of friendly although contentious exchanges between them, we must pay some heed to how Blanchot determines this crucial “concept.”

“The neuter emerges” (
EL
477/
IC 325
) in the imaginary's second version. The image is no longer related to meaning and signification but rather “tends to withdraw [the object] from its meaning by maintaining it in the immobility of a resemblance that has nothing to resemble” (
EL
350/
SH 423
, my emphasis). The image is a doubling of the object, but a neutral one, since the former appears neither as absence/presence nor as being/nothingness. The image is the hither side of objects that resists its own objective constitution and that the “elemental claims.”40 Further, this being claimed by the elemental is the very opposite of the process of idealization that the image's first version accomplishes. For this reason Blanchot chooses the corpse as the trope that will allow him not only to approach this dimension, but also to elaborate the notion of resemblance. Resemblance expresses neither the relationship between the image and its object (I 47–55), as in Sartre, nor the movement that for Levinas engenders the image. Blanchot equates the strangeness or the enigma of the image (
EL
476/
SH 331
) to the corpse that resembles itself; it is a resemblance without antecedent and, as with the image, exceeds the dialectics of presence and absence, identity and difference. Although Blanchot reads the becoming-idol of the corpse as a movement of idealization (
EL
346–47/
SH 420–21
), he quickly reverses the halting of time it brings about by focusing on the “haunting [of the] inaccessible which one cannot rid oneself of” (
EL
348/
SH 422
). Resemblance names the anarchic nature of the image, its constitutive ambiguity without reference to a previous original model.
If for Levinas the work of art bears witness to the inhuman dimension of the il y a and must be either left behind or reintegrated to the order of discourse, this is not the case with Blanchot, for whom the question is “how to experience (vivre) an event as image” (
EL
353/
SH 425
). As we saw in chapter 1, Blanchot takes as his point of departure the “space of literature” understood as the site where “the most profound question” (
EI
12–35/
IC
11–17) comes to thinking. The “space of literature” is also the site where the fascinating hold of the image liberates the irreducible ambiguity of the neuter, whose elucidation organizes Blanchot's writing in its different modalities, ranging from the novel genre and the récits to fragmentary writing.
Notes

1.

In Existence and Existents and in Time and the Other Levinas calls the movement by which a being snatches its existence from pure being hypostasis. This is an act without transcendence, the positing of a being that comes into existence and opposes itself to the il y a. In Time and the Other “the indissoluble unity between the existent and its existing” (54) is called solitude. Solitude as “a category of being” (40) does not derive its tragic character from nothingness, but from the “privation of the other.” Two important readings of the concept of evasion are Jacques Rolland, “Sortir de l'être par une nouvelle voie,” in Emmanuel Levinas, De lévasion (Paris: Fata Morgana, 1982), 10–87; and Hent de Vries, “Levinas,” in Simon Critchley and William Schroeder, eds., A Companion to Continental Philosophy (London: Blackwell, 1999), 245–55.

2.

Levinas's analysis was first published as “Il y a” in Deucalion 1 (1946): 141– 54. In a footnote he credits Blanchot's Thomas lObscure with providing a description of the il y a (EE 103/63). In “Literature and the Right to Death” Blanchot credits Levinas for having elucidated the experience of the il y a.

3.

Heidegger, Being and Time, 228–35, and “What Is Metaphysics?” in Pathmarks.

4.

“When I am alone, I am not alone, but, in this present, I am already returning to myself in the form of Someone (quelquun). Someone is there, where I am alone…. Where I am alone, I am not there; no one is there, but the impersonal is: the outside, as that which prevents, precedes, and dissolves the possibility of any personal relation with Someone (quelquun). Someone is what is still present when there is no one. When I am alone, the light of day is only the loss of a dwelling place. It is intimacy with the outside that has no location and affords no rest. Coming here makes the one who comes belong to dispersal, to the fissure where the exterior is the intrusion that stifles, but is also nakedness, the chill of the enclosure that leaves one utterly exposed. Here the only space is vertiginous separation (vertige de lespacement). Here fascination reigns” (EL 27–8/SL 31).

5.

It is necessary to stress that in Otherwise than Being the “reversal of ontological difference” is followed by its reinscription and displacement. This is a pre-condition for writing the “otherwise than being,” as Levinas explicitly states in the preface to the second edition of De lexistence à l'existant (1977) and in part as a response to Jean-Luc Marion's objections in LIdole et la distance. Levinas's treatment of Heidegger's ontological difference is a contentious issue, as evidenced in Derrida's “Violence and Metaphysics.” For an assessment of this problematic, see Silvano Petrosino, “D'un livre à l'autre: Totalité et infini et LAutrement qêtre,” in Emmanuel Lévinas, ed. Jacques Rolland (Lagrosse: Verdier, 1984); and Silvano Petrosino and Jacques Rolland, La Vérité nomade: Introduction à Emmanuel Lévinas (Paris: La Decouverte, 1984).

6.

The genealogy of this concept, according to which in the altering being of things a naked type of inwardness takes place, is Husserl's irreflexive consciousness. See Edmund Husserl, The Idea of Phenomenology: A Translation ofDie idee der Phaënomenologie,” Husserliana II, trans. Lee Hardy (Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic, 1999). This concept is akin to Merleau-Ponty's entre-deux. See Maurice MerleauPonty, “La Philosophie et son ombre,” in Signes (Paris: Gallimard, 1962), 201–28. Hereafter the work by Husserl will be cited in the text by the abbreviation IP.

7.

This type of exoticism is once again condemned in Totality and Infinity, where the allusion to Rimbaud's “je est un autre” can be read as a synecdoche for a critique of modern aesthetics from premises not very different from those of “Reality and Its Shadow.”

8.

I must stress the “as if,” since Levinas does not specify this deformalization in a positive way. The concept of obliteration that he sketches in an occasional dialogue on the work of Sosno may be the closest he comes. See Levinas, De loblitération.

9.
See
Heidegger, “The Origin of the Work of Art.”

10.

For other readings of “Reality and Its Shadow,” see Françoise Armengaud, “Éthique et esthétique: De l'ombre à l'obliteration,” in Emmanuel Lévinas, eds. Catherine Chalier and Miguel Abensour (Paris: Editions de l'Herne, 1991), 605–19; Robert Eagleston, “Cold Splendor: Levinas's Suspicion of Art,” in Ethical Criticism: Reading after Levinas (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1997); Jill Robbins, “Aesthetic Totality and Ethical Infinity,” in Altered Reading: Levinas and Literature (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 75–90; and Thomas C. Wall, “The Allegory of Being,” in Radical Passivity: Levinas, Blanchot and Agamben

(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999), 13–30.

11.

See Jean-Paul Sartre, “Qu'estce que la littérature?” in Situations II (Paris: Gallimard, 1964) and Heidegger, “The Origin of the Work of Art.” Hereafter the Sartre work will cited in the text by the abbreviation QL.

12.

Emmanuel Levinas, “Realité et son ombre,” Les Temps Modernes 25 (1948). Malka attributes the note's authorship to Maurice Merleau-Ponty. See Salomon Malka, Lire Lévinas (Paris: Cerf, 1984), 32. The French reads: “Les ideés de Sartre sur l'engagement de la littérature n'on été examinées qu’à moitié.”

13.

See Eugen Fink, “Vergegenwärtigung und Bild: Beiträge zur Phänomenologie der Unwirklichkeit,” in Studien zur Phänomenologie, 1930–39 (The Hague: M. Nijhoff, 1966), 71–72. This essay was originally written in 1927.

14.

Emmanuel Levinas, Collected Philosophical Papers. trans. Alphonso Lingis (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1998). Hereafter, this work is cited in the text by the abbreviation CPP.

15.

See chapter 3.

16.

Levinas's aesthetic conceptuality belongs to a French literary and philosophical tradition whose points of origin are Alain and Paul Valéry. It is Sartre who popularizes this tradition. Some of the main tenets of this tradition are: the clear distinction of color and sound from words, the distinction between sound and image, the opaque nature of sensation, and the placing of art on the hither side of form's material values.

17.

For an argument that develops the possibilities of an ethical face-to-face in writing, see A. Ponzio, Sujet et alterité sur Emmanuel Lévinas (Paris: L'Harmattan, 1996), 28.

18.

Levinas's critique of classic art generally follows Rosenzweig's analysis of pagan art and the anti-iconic Jewish tradition that issues from Maimonides.

19.

Emile Benveniste, “La Notion de ‘rythme’ dans son expression linguistique,” in Problèmes de linguistique générale 1 (Paris: Gallimard, 1966), 327–35.

20.

Henri Meschonic, Critique du rythme (Paris: Verdier, 1990).

21.

R. Court, “Rythme, tempo, mésure,” Revue desthétique 2 (1974): 148–50.

22.

Court, “Rhythm, tempo, measure,” 148.

23.

For the conceptual solidarity of the language of Totality and Infinity with a metaphysics of presence, see Derrida, “Violence and Metaphysics,” in WAD. For the performative dimension of Otherwise than Being, see Thomas Wiemer, “Das Unsagbare sagen,” in Levinas eds. M. Mayer and M. Hentschel, Parabel 12 (Giessen: Focus Verlag, 1990), 21; and Derrida, “En ce moment même dans cette ouvrage me voici,” in PSY.

24.

I am here following Edith Wyschogrod's “The Art in Ethics,” in Adriaan Peperzak, ed., Ethics as First Philosophy (New York: Routledge, 1995), 137–50.

25.

Edmund Husserl, Cartesian Meditations (Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer, 1995); Jean-Paul Sartre, LImaginaire (Paris: Gallimard, 1940), which was translated as The Psychology of the Imagination (London: Routledge, 1995). Hereafter, the Husserl work will be cited by the abbreviation CM, the English version of Sartre's work by PI, and the original French by I.

26.

“The unreal is produced outside the world by a consciousness which stays in the world and it is because he is transcendentally free that man can imagine” (I 248/PI 216).

27.

In a 1984 essay, “Interdit de la représentation et droits de l'homme,” Levinas questions the representational horizon of a phenomenology that takes the body as its point of departure in its appresentation of the other and asks if “sous la méfiance recommandée par le monothéisme juif relativement aux représentations et aux images d’être, ne se dénonce pas, dans les sructures de la signifiance et du sensé, un certain prévaloir de la représentation sur des autres modalités possibles de la pensée.” Levinas is here questioning the privilege representation enjoys in phenomenology, in its determination of intentionality, even in the case of a phenomenology of perception like Merleau-Ponty's. Levinas claims that “l'interdit de la représentation suggérerait au contraire dans le sensé une transcendance par rapport à laquelle celle de l'intentionnalité n'aura été qu'un enfermement dans une conscience de soi.” See Levinas, Altérité et transcendance (Montpellier: Fata Morgana, 1995), 130; 133. Hereafter, this work is cited in the text by the abbreviation AT.

28.

See Catherine Chalier, “The Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas and the Hebraic Tradition,” Robert Gibbs, “Height and Nearness: Jewish Dimensions of Radical Ethics,” and Charles Scott, “A People's Witness beyond Politics,” in Peperzak, ed., Ethics as First Philosophy, 3–38; Charles Mopsik, “La Pensée d'Emmanuel Lévinas et la Cabbale,” in Emmanuel Lévinas, eds. Catherine Chalier and Miguel Abensour (Paris: Èditions de l'Herne, 1991), 428–41; Idoles: Données et débats, Actes du XXIVe Colloque des Intellectuels Juifs de Langue Française (Paris: Denöel, 1985); Catherine Chalier, “L'Interdit de la représentation,” La Trace de linfini: Emmanuel Levinas et la source hébraïque (Paris: Cerf, 2002), 253–67.

29.

Chalier's discussion of the different positions in the debate on the prohibition of images in the Jewish tradition seems to indicate an oscillation between a complete condemnation, especially when the object of representation is the human face, and the position that sees in the use of the image a tentative orientation in the direction of the invisible so as to better celebrate it and for which art becomes a form of praying. See “L'Interdit de la représentation,” 256–57.

30.

For the question of “saturated phenomena” and the approach to the invisible beyond being, see Jean-Luc Marion, LIdole et la distance (Paris: Grasset, 1977); Étant donné: La Croisée du visible (Paris: Èditions de la Différence, 1996); God Without Being (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991), 25–52; and In Excess: Studies of Saturated Phenomena, trans. Robyn Horner and Vincent Berraud (New York: Fordham University Press, 2002).

31.

See Franz Rosenzweig, The Star of Redemption, trans. Barbara E. Galli (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 2005), 117–18. Here he defines the language of art as the language of the “before-world.” For a comparative study of Levinas see Robert Gibbs, Correlations in Rosenzweig and Levinas (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992).

32.

See also Levinas, “Lévy-Bruhl et la philosophie contemporaine” in Entre nous. According to Jill Robbins, participation “describes primitive mentality's mystic belief in the unseen, supernatural forces, its emotional and affective relation to collective representations, which are perceived as having a transitive influence…. Participation [is] a way of thinking indifferent to the law of contradiction.” See Jill Robbins, Altered Readings (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 86–89.

33.

For a comprehensive study of Heidegger's ontology of the world, see Michel Haar, The Song of the Earth: Heidegger and the Grounds of the History of Being, trans. Reginald Lilly (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1993).

34.

There are several signs of this appeasement: Levinas's explicit recognition of his debt to Heidegger's thinking in Otherwise than Being; his way of rethinking the place of being in the general economy of the “otherwise than being” ; as well as his reassessment of technology's value in “Idéologie et idéalisme” (1972), published in Of God Who Comes to Mind and of the work of art in Otherwise than Being. See Levinas, Of God Who Comes to Mind, trans. Bettina Bergo (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998). Hereafter, this work is cited in the text by the abbreviation GCM.

35.

See “Preface à la deuxieme edition,” in De lexistance à l'existant (Paris: Vrin, 1963), 11–12. This preface dates from 1981 and is not included in the English translation. Hereafter the French version is cited in the text by the abbreviation DEE.

36.

Emmanuel Levinas, Hors sujet (Montpellier: Fata Morgana, 1972). Hereafter, this work is cited in the text by the abbreviation HS.

37.

Levinas, Noms propres (Montpellier: Fata Morgana, 1976). Hereafter, this work is cited in the text by the abbreviation NP.

38.

The most in-depth study of figuration in Levinas is John Llewelyn, Emmanuel Levinas: The Genealogy of Ethics (London: Routledge, 1995), 162–96.

39.

In chapter 6 we will see that the introduction of a human dimension at the heart of difference takes place in Blanchot's reading of Levinas's Totality and Infinity.

40.

“In the image, the object again touches something it had mastered in order to be an object, something against which it had built and defined itself, but now that its value, its signification, is suspended, now that the world is abandoning it to worklessness (désœuvrement) and putting it to one side, the truth in it withdraws, the elemental claims it, which is the impoverishment, the enrichment that consecrates it as image” (EL 343–4/SH 419).

Close
This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

Close

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

View Article Abstract & Purchase Options

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

Close